http://wormholetravel.net/
We have had
occasion to refer to the notion of a "model" or an
"interpretation" of a math theory constructed with the help of
another theory. This is not a recent idea, and it should undoubtedly be seen as
a continually recurring manifestation of a deep-lying feeling of the unity of
the various "math sciences". If the traditional maxim "All things
are numbers" of the early Pythagoreans is taken as authentic, it may be
considered as the vestige of a first attempt to reduce the geometry and algebra
of the time to arithmetic.
The
increasingly widespread use of the notion of "model" was to permit the
nineteenth-century mathematicians to achieve the unification of maths dreamed
of by the Pythagoreans. At the beginning of the century, whole numbers and
continuous quantities were as irreconcilable as they had been in antiquity; the
real numbers were related to the notion of geometric magnitude (especially that
of length), and the "models" of negative numbers and imaginary
number! were constructed on this basis. Even the rational numbers were
traditionally associated with the idea of "subdivision" of magnitude
into equal parts. Only the integers remained apart, as "exclusive products
of our intellect", as Gauss said in 1832.
The first
attempts to bring together arithmetic and analysis were concerned with the
rational numbers (positive and negative); they were taken up around 1860 by
several authors, notably Grassman, Hankel, and Weierstrass. To Weierstrass is,
apparently, due the idea of obtaining a "model" of the positive of
negative rational numbers by considering classes of ordered pairs of natural
integers. But the most important step still remained to be taken, namely, to
construct a "model" of the
irrational numbers from within the theory of rational numbers.
By 1870 this
had become an urgent problem because of the necessity, after the discovery of "pathological"
phenomena in analysis, to purge every
trace of geometrical intuition and the vague notion of "magnitude"
from the definition of real numbers. The problem was, in fact, solved at about
this time almost simultaneously Cantor, Dedekind, Meray and Weierstrass, using
quite different methods from one another.
From then on,
the integers became the foundation of all classical maths. Furthermore, the "models" founded on arithmetic
acquired still greater importance with the extension of the axiomatic method
and the conception of math objects as free creations of the human intellect.
For there remained a limitation to the freedom claimed by Cantor, namely, the
limitation raised by the question of "existence " which had already
occupied the Greeks, and which arose now so much more urgently precisely because all appeal to
intuitive representation was now abondoned.
We shall not
discuss what a philosophico-math maelstrom was to be generated by notion of
"existence" in the early years of the twentieth century. But in the nineteenth century this stage had not yet been
reached, and to prove the existence of a math object having a given set of
properties meant simply, just as Euclid, "to construct" an object
with the required properties. This was purpose of the arithmetical
"models".
Once the
real numbers had been "interpreted" in terms of integers, then the same
was done for complex numbers and Euclidean geometry, thanks to analytic geometry,
and likewise for all the new algebraic objects introduced since the beginning'
of the century. Finally, in a discovery which achieved great fame Beltrami and Klein
obtained Euclidean "models" of the non-Euclidean geometries of Lobachevsky
and Riemann and thereby "arithmetized" (and completely justified)
these theories which at first had aroused so much distrust.
Комментариев нет:
Отправить комментарий