http://wormholetravel.net/math.html
Three new
approaches to numbers, in 1801 and in the 1830s, were to hint at the general concept
of math structure and reveal unsuspected horizons in the whole of maths. That
of 1801 was the concept of congruence, introduced by ( muss. To this and the
revolutionary work (1830) of E. Galois in the theory of algebraic equations can
be traced the partial execution of L. Kronecker's (1823 - 1891) programme in
the 1880s for basing all maths on the natural numbers.
The same
sources are one origin of the modern abstract development of algebruic and
geometric theories, in which the structure of math systems is the sub-led of
investigation, and it is sought to obtain the interrelations of the math
objects concerned with a minimum of calculation. "Structure" may be
thought of at present in any of its intuitive meanings; it was precisely
defined in 1910 by the math logicians. We shall approach math structure through
the union effected In the nineteenth century between algebra and arithmetic.
From the
standpoint of maths as a whole, the methodology of deliberate generalozation
and abstraction, culminating in the twentieth century in a rapidly glowing
maths of structure, is doubtless the most significant contribution of all the
successive attempts to extend the number concept. But at every stage of the
progression from the natural numbers 1, 2, 3,... to other types of numbers,
each ill several fields of maths adjacent to arithmetic was broadened and
enriched.
New
acquisitions in other fields reacted reciprocally on arithmetic. For example,
the first satisfactory theory of ordinary complex numbers to become widely
known was that of Gauss (1831) devised to provide a concise solution for a special
problem in Diophantine analysis.
The theory
of complex numbers necessitated a radical revision and generalization of the
concept of arithmetical divisibility, which in turn suggested a reformulation
of certain parts of algebraic geometry. The latter, in its turn, was partly
responsible for further generalizations (modular systems) in the algebraic
arithmetic - or arithmetical algebra — of the twentieth century. The forward
movement was universal and each major advance in one department induced
progress in others.
The passage
to final abstractness took about a quarter of a century. The turning point was
Hilbert's work on the foundation of geometry in 1899. Although this did not
concern algebra or arithmetic directly, it set a new and high standard of
definiteness and completeness in the statement of all math definitions or, what
is equivalent, in the construction of postulate systems. A general theory of
structure was developed by A. N. Whitehead and B. Russell in 1910.
It will
suffice here to recall a cardinal definition: A relation p between the members of a set Xp has the same structure
as a relation q between the members
of a set Yq if there is a one-to-one correspondence between the elements of Xq and
Yp such that, whenever two elements of Xp are in the relation p to each other, their correlates (by
the correspondence) in Yq are in the relation q to each other, and vice versa. Modern developments of numbers and
their influence on the emergence of structure, the greatly generalized concept
of whole number, or integer, distinguished the higher arithmetic of the late
nineteenth century from all that had preceded it.
There are
six major developments in maths that greatly influenced the modern theory of
numbers. They are: 1) the definition by Gauss, Kummer and Dede kind of
algebraic integers; 2) the restoration of the fundamental theorem of arithmetic
in algebraic number fields by Dedekind's introduction of ideals; 3) the definitive
work of Galois on the solution of algebraic equations by radicals; 4) the
theory of finite groups; 5) the modern theory of fields that followed; 6) the
partial application of arithmetical concepts to certain linear algebras.
All of these
developments are closely interrelated. The last marks the farthest extension of
classical arithmetic up to 1945, and it is either the climax or the beginning
of a structural arithmetization of algebra, foreseen as early as 1860 by
Kronecker. As if in preparation for the climax, the algebra of hypercomplex numbers
rapidly outgrew its classificatory adolescence of the 1870s and became progressively
more concerned with general methods reaching a certain maturity early in the
twentieth century.
The fifth
major development, which logically would seem to be a necessary prelude to the
others, strangely enough came last. Not until the closing years of the
nineteenth century was anyone greatly perturbed about the natural numbers 1, 2,
3, ... . All maths, from the classical arithmetic to Fermat, Euler, Lagrange,
Legendre, Gauss and their numerous imitators, to geometry and analysis, had
accepted these speciously simple numbers as "given". Without them,
none of the major advances of modern arithmetic would ever have happened.
Yet no arithmetician
asked, "By whom are the natural numbers 'given'"? Kronecker ascribed
them to God, but this was hardly a math solution. The question arose, not in
arithmetic, but in analysis. It was answered by the modern definition of
cardinal and ordinal numbers. This finally united arithmetic and analysis at
their common source.
The sixth
and last major development in the evolution of the number concept was the
application of arithmetic to the differential and integral calculus. It is a
point of great interest that one of the strongest initial impulses for the
final application of arithmetic to analysis came from math physics. It was
gradually perceived that the cardinals and ordinals 1, 2, 3, ...demanded
clarification. The arithmetic of 1,2, 3,..., and with it math analysis,
resigned its soul to the searching mercies of math logic.
About
twenty-five centuries of struggle to understand numbers thus ended where it had
begun with Pythagoras. The modern programme is his, but with a difference.
Pythagoras trusted 1, 2, 3, ... to "explain" the Universe including
maths, and the spirit animating his "explanation" was strict
deductive reasoning. The natural numbers are still trusted by mathematicians
and scientists in their technical maths and its applications. But math
reasoning itself, vastly broadened and deepened in the twentieth century beyond
the utmost ever imagined by any Greek, supplanted the natural numbers in math
interest.
When, if
ever, math logic shall have surmounted its obscurities, the natural numbers may
be clearly seen for what they "are". But there will always remain the
possibility that any unsealed range may conceal a higher just beyond, and arithmeticians
will come upon many things to keep them busy and incompletely satisfied for the
next five thousand years. After that, perhaps, it will not matter to Anyone
that 1, 2, 3, ... "are".
From the
great mass of work that has been done since 1900 on the arithmization of
algebra — or vice versa — one should mention the study of all possible types of
fields and the relations between them.
The final
outcome may be roughly described as an analysis of the structure of fields with
respect to their possible subfields and super fields. The next item, dating
from about 1920 marks a distinct advance. It is represented by a host of mathematicians
who undertook to do for an abstract ring what Dedekind has done for any ring of
algebraic numbers, and to extend the Galois theory to abstract fields.
Thus, the
Dedekind theory of ideals was abstracted and generalized, as was also the
Galois theory. The first of these may properly be assigned to arithmetic, it.
one of the chief objectives is the discovery, for any ring, of unique decomposition
theorems analogous to the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, or to the unique
representation of a Dedekind ideal as a product of prime ideals. Two basic
but rather inconspicuous-looking items of the classical theory of Algebraic
number ideals passed unchanged into the abstract theory, "the greatest
common divisor (the GCD)" and "least common multiple (LCM)".
Although at the first glance these are mere details, experience has shown that
they are the framework of much algebraic structure and that, when their
simplest properties are restated abstractly as postulates, the resulting system
unifies widely separated and apparently distinct theories of algebra and
arithmetic. They lead, in fact, to what seemed the most important theory of
algebraic-arithmetic structures.
The rapid
expansion of the theory of structures or
lattices following Dedekind's Introduction of dual groups is typical of
much in the recent development of maths.
Комментариев нет:
Отправить комментарий